Sides of the Law
I haven't spoken about last week's attack on a gay club in Orlando, but I'm going to try to do so now in light of one scholar's response about how we can live collectively with deep differences.
I didn't talk much about the attack because I'm not gay, like those targeted by the terrorist, or Muslim, like those targeted by the state, and I believe the challenge for people in that position is not to speak out but listen carefully and be open to what we hear.
A problem with this approach is that it can often seem like doing nothing at all. But standing with gay, and Muslim, people in my life is something, to echo recent some thoughtful words, I don't want to leave undone.
I don't know how to do that now.
I do think, however, that it is one part of a field of moral and political questions about the recognition of others and other spaces even as we work toward common purposes.
With that in mind I read this piece by Jonathan Brown about gay marriage, Islamic law, and "safeguarding each other's rights in a pluralist society."
Brown's work has attracted the praise it has from academics, Muslim ʿulamāʾ, and non-scholars in part for his ability to bring complexities into focus with the posing of simple, meaningful questions, qualities this article shows. Yet, I think it has some problems that I'll try to address by posing some different questions and frames to Brown's analysis of fiqh, Islamic legal thought.
The question I asked is: what we can premodern Islamic legal thinking teach us about living with abiding differences.
This is a question Brown is interested in, but here he is asking something else: what limits did premodern Islamic jurists placed on their tolerance for protected minority (dhimmī) communities, and what does this mean for Muslims in America, who might dissent considerably from public policies but who are not in the same legal framework.
He covers the extensive range of practices jurists recognized or agreed to put up with among dhimmīs that Islamic law cannot abide. Jurists recognized sibling marriages among Zoroastrians. Muslim judges helped Christians evaluate the price of wine stocks. Centuries of Muslim rule did not change Iberian tastes for ham.
Brown is not saying no Muslim rulers had legal justification to stop minority practices they disapproved of, he is saying that he has found jurists tolerating those practices because of the way the sharīʿa defers to non-Muslim communities to constitute realms of their own under Muslim subordination.
Nevertheless, he concludes, juristic thinkers could not have countenanced gay marriage, as we think of it, even among non-Muslims under Muslim protection.
This isn't the point in contemporary America, he stresses, because US law is not meaningfully influenced by Mughal India or Mamluk Egypt. In a liberal, Muslim-minority society like ours, everyone must respect others' rights to organize communities peacefully according to their own consciences, vigilantism should never be tolerated, and the state should not force gay acceptance on those who peacefully will not accept.
It isn't that I object to any points he makes, and my research has not taken the same range his has, so I have no claim that he's missed anything.
I would rather make a slightly different generalization than him and say that what jurists have accepted of non-Muslims is a factor of what they encountered.
I don't think it would be unreasonable historical fiction to imagine Muslim legal authorities having space for same-sex marriage rites of Episcopalians or Reform Jews. They just did not to encounter and rule over these communities historically, so they could not have considered it.
More important than historical fiction, however, is the range of historical experience. Brown tells us that Muslim rule accommodated traditions much more widely different than those named in the Qurʾān, despite the dangerously popular misconception. Not only were fellow monotheists undisturbed because of Muslim regard for their scriptures, Muslim states regarded Hindus, with their multiplicities of devotion, and Confucians, with their disinterest in the gods, as dhimmīs.
The lesson I would draw from this, and have been trying to articulate in my own work, is about the exteriors of the state in premodern politics. Examples I am working on: even as Chinese states were sometimes rigidly defined by Confucian orthodoxies, outside official life, people partook of plurally different spiritual life-ways. One person could take part in many traditions.
Similarly, the multifaith Muslim empires practiced precolonial forms of modesty that can be instructive to us in may ways. They looked to different communities to co-constitute shared spaces like markets and military ventures without the enforced binding of Westphalia-style regimes.
I don't think Western or colonial-inspired notions of politics, centered on the state, liberal or not, have much of any exteriority.
To understand these past exteriorities, I think we can look differently at how law divided inside and outside spaces and people. So in this, I am focusing less on the limits of its tolerance strictly speaking.
My thinking about these examples differs somewhat from Brown's, but I think we have a common critique of the idea that metaphysical certainties invariably connect to violence: modern history has so little of the first and so much of the second. So this secularist credo needs rethinking.
Similarly, we might both agree that liberal ideas about how to accommodate difference in part account for atomistic and conformist forces in modern life. We should be open to different ways of understanding difference.
That process of consideration doesn't come easily when are not safe. This kind of thinking does not sit easily in the cycles of violence and alarm that surround us. Scholars of religion can have some perspective on these situations and the assumptions that give rise to them. It is not always their place to speak up, but it is to reflect critically.